Williams wants to argue that immortality--or a life without
death--would be meaningless, or that death gives meaning to life. Let
us call this position the Makropolus
Position:
Makropolus Position: that
death gives life meaning, and that an immortal life would be meaningless.
Williams begins by presenting two arguments in favor of an opposing
position, one which we have called in class the Epicurean View:
Epicurean View: death is
neither an evil nor a good; it neither makes life meaningful nor
meaningles; death is nothing to us.
(Notice that the
Epicurean view technically says that death is evaluatively neutral--i.e., it is neither an
evil nor a good. In this article, however, and in a majority of the
others we will be looking at, we are primarily concerned with whether
death is an evil. So we have
left discussion of whether death is a good alone for now. However, do
notice that the following discussion could be run concerning death as
good, as opposed to evil. You might see for yourself whether you think
parallel moves can be made if someone were to try to argue that death
was a good thing, and consider why someone might think this.)
Williams' strategy is to show how the two arguments for the Epicurean View fail, and how this
fact, together with some additional considerations, buttress support
for the Makropolus Position. The two arguments in support of the
Epicurean view are as follows:
Argument 1:
(1) If death is an evil, then we must experience it as evil.
(2) Death is an experiential blank; we can never experience death as
evil.
(C) Therefore, death is not an evil.
Argument 2:
(1) If death is an evil, then more of it should make a difference than
less of it--i.e., we should prefer less
death than more.
(2) Once you are dead, you are dead for the same amount of
time--FOREVER--so more of it doesn't make a difference than less of it.
(C) Therefore, death is not an evil.
In Argument 1, premise
(1) follows from a general Epicurean Priniple:
Epicurean Principle: something is good or bad for a
person if and only if that person experiences
it as good or bad;
nothing can be bad for a person if that person does not experience it
as bad.
We talked about the Epicurean
Principle in relation to Nagel's article, "Death." Recall that Nagel
argued against this principle because he thought that there were plenty
of counterexamples: lies, betrayal, infidelity, etc., are all cases
where it seems that something is bad for a person, even if that person
never finds out. So given what Nagel says in his article, we can assume
that he would reject premise (1) of Argument 1.
But what about Argument 2? Premise (1) seems pretty intuitive: usually,
if something is evil, then more of it will
make a difference--i.e., we would prefer less of it than
more. One murder is bad; more murders is even
worse. Getting an F in class is bad; getting more Fs is even worse,
etc. And premise (2) seems intuitive as well: if once you are
dead, you are dead forever, then being dead one year more or less
really won't make a difference in the amount of time you are dead--it
is still for eternity either way.
Williams, however, thinks that there are several things wrong with
Argument 2. First, he thinks that there is a dangerous tension between
Argument 1 and Argument 2--he thinks that Argument 2 indirectly
contradcts Argument (1). To show this, Wiliams claims that premise (2)
of Argument 2 implies the following counterfactual (*):
(*)
If there were a finite
period of death (i.e., if death were not
eternal), such that if you died later rather then sooner then
you would be dead for less
time, then there would be a
point to wanting to die later rather than earlier.
And Williams thinks that (*) can only be true if there is
something wrong with the condition
of being dead. But this is
exactly what is denied by Argument 1! There is nothing that it is like
to be dead; death is an experiential blank!
Response
One might respond to Williams as follows: "By definition, death cannot
be a finite period of time. Death is the permanent cessation of life. So it
is logically impossible for death to be of finite duration. Thus, (*)
has a logically impossible antecedent. Entertaining such a counterpossible would be as absurd as
entertaining the counterpossible "If 2 +2 = 5, then ______." So
Argument 2 cannot imply (*), unless there is an absurdity in Argument 2
itself, in which case it would be open to a redutio ad absurdum. Since it is
not, (*) is neither here nor there, and is of no concern to the
Epicurean."
However, Williams has a
second, less contentious charge against the arguments for the Epicurean
View. He charges that the Epicurean will admit that there are goods in
life--praemia vitae. We have
goals and desires and needs, and when these are accomplished, there is
an uncontroversial positive value to our life. Being conscious of the
rewards and delights of life is itself a reward and delight, and even
the Epicurean will admit as much. But, if this is right (Williams
argues) then being around longer--staving off death for as long as
possible--living longer so that you can reap these goods in life is
prefeable to having a life cut short. So, a longer life is, all else
being equal, better than a shorter one. And so a later death is
prefered to a sooner one. But this directly contradticts premise (2) of
Argument 2, and so something must be wrong with Argument (2).
To further support the claim that a longer life is prefered to a
shorter one, Williams presents the following principle:
Principle of Desire: If I
desire something, then (other things being equal) I prefer a state of
affairs in which I get it from one in which I do not.
Suppose the Principle of
Desire is true. Well, no matter what the desire (so Williams argues), a
situation in which I am alive rather than dead is one in which I might
get what I desire. In other words, being dead is guarenteed to
frustrate any desire I have, and so given the Principle of Desire, I
will prefer situations in which I am alive over ones in which I am not.
So wanting anything is a reason to avoid death. Knowing that death will
frustrate any of your wants and desires is enough to make death an
evil, from the point of view of a wanting agent. All wants are
conditional on being alive.
However, Williams does not
exactly endorse the above argument himself; he seems to think there is
something appealing about it, but in the end thinks that one can have
categorical, as opposed to a conditional desire. In the case of
suicide, for example, it may just be that an individual has the
categorical desire not to live, and this better not be conditional upon
anything else. He also raises the possibility of an ascetic who has the
brute, categorical desire to live. But none of this really matters,
Williams thinks, since we may be able to cash out the difference in
terms of possible worlds.
[to be continued...]
Page
Last Updated: 4/15/08