Modal
Realism
Davd Lewis’ Modal Realism is misleadingly named. A better name for his view would be ‘Possible Worlds Realism.’ This is because while many people are realists about modality, or modal facts, not many people are realists about the entities that the modal facts are analyzed in terms of—viz., possible worlds. Here’s why: it has been widely agreed that it is extremely theoretically useful to analyze modal talk in terms of possible worlds as follows: possibly p iff in some possible world, p; necessarily p iff in all possible worlds, p. Further, without such a reduction, the notions of ‘possibly’ and ‘necessarily’ would have to be taken as primitive, which is seen as an ontological mystery (and, thus, a theoretical burden). However, if the possible worlds analysis of modal terms is adopted, we now have a new problem: we are seemingly quantifying over possible worlds and, if we are good Quineans, we are now committed to having such worlds in our ontology. Moreover, we are now pressed to say just what these possible worlds are.
Lewis boldly claims that possible worlds are of the same ontological kind as the actual world—where the actual world, he claims, is intuitively anything that is spatio-temporally and causally connected with us, here. More technically, the actual world—like other possible worlds—is a maximal, consistent set of spatio-temporally and causally connected stuff. Anything that is any spatial or temporal distance from us is part of our world; anything that’s not, isn’t. Other possible worlds, Leiws claims, are just like ours. They are maximal, consistent sets of spatio-temporally and causally connected stuff. Anything that is any spatial or temporal distance from (world-bound) people in other possible worlds is part of their world; anything that’s not, isn’t. Individuals in these possible worlds—including our own—are world-bound; they cannot move from one world to the next. By definition, any world or place they could ‘get to’ would be somewhere in their own world.Lewis thinks that the main reason to be a modal realist is because doing so is so theoretically beneficial. In other words, if analyzing modal terms in terms of possible worlds is so useful, and such an analysis honestly requires quantification over possible worlds, then (as any good Quinean knows) this is enough to posit possible worlds in our ontology. Put yet another way, Lewis is committed to the following general, Quinean principle: if our best theory about the world quantifies over certain entities, then we are committed to having such entities in our ontology. Our best theory of modality, Lewis claims, is committed to possible worlds, so we mustn’t deny that there really are such things.
Lewis parallels this move about ontological commitment to the debates in the ontology in mathematics. At least on the surface, mathematics quantifies over abstract entities such as sets, numbers, functions, etc. However, even though having such entities in our ontology might be ontologically costly, doing so provides us with so much theoretical benefits that the price seems worth it. Put more generally, there is always a trade-off between theoretical benefits and ontological costs. If the benefits received outweigh the costs, then it is seen as a worthwhile trade. Lewis thinks that not only is the trade worthwhile when it comes to modal realism, but what’s more, no other theory about modality will fare near as well. [More on this last point below.]To help massage our (likely) resistance to his view, he makes a distinction between qualitative and quantitative ontological costs. Since, according to Lewis, possible worlds are not ontologically different kinds of things, his modal realism is only demanding a quantitative ontological cost. He claims that his view simply posits more of what we already think there is. All (or most) of us are already committed to the actual world, no matter what one’s view of modality or possible worlds. So, in committing oneself to modal realism, Lewis thinks, you are simply committing yourself to more of what is already in your ontology. Instead of one world, there’s many. But it’s not as if the many worlds are anything spooky or new or are a kind of entity that we should be suspicious of, on ontological grounds. Modal Realism, then, isn’t claiming that there are totally different kinds of things (like, say, dualism would if one is a materialist). Thus, Lewis thinks that (i) the theoretical benefits are worth the ontological costs of modal realism and (ii) that the ontological costs aren’t as great as they might initially seem anyway, since it is only a quantitative, not a qualitative cost.
Moreover, with
modal realism, Lewis thinks, we get
a nice
way to reduce or analyze our somewhat mysterious, intensional modal
talk, with
non-mysterious, extensional talk of possible worlds. If we had
difficulty
understanding what it meant for something to be possible or necessary,
in other
words, possible worlds will help us, conceptually, to understand modal
truths.
We know what it is for someone to be lounging on the beach, for
example. And we
seemingly know what it would be for someone very much like me (in the
relevant
ways) to be lounging around on the beach. This is enough, then, Lewis
argues,
to understand what it is for it to be possible that I am lounging on a
beach.
For, so long as there is a possible world in which a counterpart of me
(i.e.,
someone very much like me in relevant ways) is lounging around on a
beach, this
is what makes it true that it’s possible that I could be lounging
around on a
beach. This gets us into issues about his counterpart theory, which I
will
address below.
Further
Details of the View
Trans-World Identity: There are two sorts of problems that people seem to have in mind when they talk about the problem of trans-world identity. One is epistemological, the other, metaphysical. The epistemological worry runs as follows: if we are inclined to think that possible worlds are like distant countries or planets, then we might think that we will have a problem finding or picking out certain individuals. For if we only have the external, physical properties to go by, we will have a difficult time discerning certain objects from the qualitative duplicates of those objects. But intuitively, there is a difference between, say, Nixon, and someone who merely looks like Nixon, and has all the external, descriptive features of Nixon. So the epistemological worry involved in the problem of trans-world identity is that we will not be able to tell an individual from his look-a-like when we are searching through all of the possible worlds. (By the way, this is the worry that Kripke seems most concerned with when he’s discussing trans-world identity in Naming and Necessity. It also seems that this is related to one of Lewis’ worries about linguistic ersatzism concerning the (seeming) lack of descriptive power or descriptive resources that the ersatzer has at his disposal.)
The metaphysical
worry, however, involves whether
the
relation that’s held between people in different possible worlds can
ever be
one of identity. For example, if we thought that possible worlds were
concrete
things, that they really were something like very far way and distant
planets,
then there seems to be a difficulty in saying that one and the same
individual
can occupy two or more different possible worlds. We say that it’s
possible
that I am on a beach in
Quantifier Restriction: An initial worry some might have with Lewis’ modal realism is the following: “when we say there are things, we mean to be committed to them, ontologically, but we also mean that these things actually are. Whenever we are ontologically committed to things, in other words, we are ontologically committed to them existing in the actual world. So it doesn’t make sense to say that purple gnomes and magic beans and innumerably many fat men in doorways are, but that these thing are not actual, like Lewis wants us to do.”
In response to this sort of worry, Lewis argues that our use of ‘there are’ is contextually sensitive. Imagine, for example, that we were at a party and after looking at the sorry contents (or lack of contents) of the fridge, someone exclaims: “There’s no more beer!” Surely, we will think that what this someone is saying is true; after all, his exclamation is what motivates a bunch of us to pile in a car and head out on a beer run. But we do not thereby think that he meant that there is no more beer anywhere. That is part of the reason we left for the store to get more beer; we thought there was more to be had. It’s just that there wasn’t anymore beer at the party. Examples like these abound, Lewis thinks. What we are doing in such cases, he explains, is trading on contextually sensitive quantifiers. When we use quantifier words such as ‘everything’, ‘nothing’, ‘there are’, ‘most’, etc., we can restrict our quantifiers in each case to include just the things around here, or those things a bit further out, or we can use them completely unrestrictedly and talk about everything, everywhere. This is what is happening, Lewis thinks, when we talk about what there is. When we say that there are no purple gnomes or magic beans or innumerably many fat men in the doorway, our quantifiers are restricted to the actual world, and all of what we think is in it. When we force our quantifiers wide open, however, and want to account not only for what there actually is, but what there is tout court, then we will, Lewis thinks, say that there are purple gnomes and magic beans and whatever else we think is possible as well as what’s actual. Or at least, this is what we will say if Lewis is right.
‘Actual’ is an
Indexical: Another distinguishing
feature of Lewis’ modal realism is his claim that ‘actual’ is an
indexical. To
aid our intuitions here, Lewis considers parallel indexicals such as
‘here’ or
‘now.’ If I say in
Why Modal Realism is Better than the Alternatives: Lewis thinks that modal realism is better than any of its competitors for several reasons. Concentrating just on the realist alternatives for now, Lewis thinks that his view is better than any of the ersatz views mostly because his view seems to have fewer descriptive limitations and more descriptive resources than the alternatives.
Lewis
would simply
claim that the theoretical benefits outweigh
the ontological costs.
Too Epistemically Mysterious:
One concern
we might
have with Lewis’ Modal Realism is that it is too epistemically
mysterious.
Lewis claims that what ground our modal truths are the things that
happen in
spatio-temporally and causally isolated possible worlds. But, how, we
might
wonder, can something that happens in a world that is spatio-temporally
and
causally isolated from us have any effect whatsoever in the modal
properties we
have here and now. What’s more, even if this view of modality were
true, how
could we ever know what was happening in other possible worlds? If
other
possible worlds are spatio-temporally and causally isolated from us,
then how
could I ever find out what other people are really doing in other
possible
words? And if we have no way of finding out what they are doing, then
how can
we ever find out what the modal truth are, and so how can we know
whether
anything is possible or necessary?
Lewis’ response here is to invoke what’s known as Benacerraff’s Dilemma. In the philosophy of mathematics, for example, we can either deny that our talk of mathematics is useful (or deny that it really is quantifying over mathematical entities), or we could deny that the only way we can come to know things is causally. In the one case, we are letting our metaphysics be guided by an empiricist epistemology, in the other, we are letting our epistemology be guided by our metaphysics, or at least letting our epistemology be guided by the sorts of entities that our language quantifies over. If we find mathematics and mathematical talk indispensable, and irreducible, however—i.e., if we can’t find a way to reduce such talk to something more metaphysically friendly—then we might be inclined to plunk down for mathematical entities in our ontology rather than an empiricist-friendly epistemology. It’s all a matter of trade-offs and theoretical benefits, Lewis thinks. And like philosophy of mathematics, Lewis argues, we should decide in favor of metaphysics over epistemology in the case of modality and possible worlds.
The Argument from Concern: This objection can be rather simply stated, and I think originated with Rosen (in his Modal Fictionalism article). It goes like this: “Look, I care about whether I could have been a millionaire, or could have gone out with that one guy if I would have just let him beat me at pool, or could have passed the metaphysics exam if I would have studied just a bit more diligently, etc. I care, in other words, about certain modal facts about me, about what I could and could not have done, or what is possible or not possible for me to do in the future. But I do not care about what someone very much like me in some possible world way too far away does! I don’t even really care about what someone very much like me one state over is doing. So why should I care what someone very much like me in a spatio-temporally and causally isolated possible world is doing? That I care for one thing so very much (e.g., my own modal facts), and care about the other so very, very little (e.g., some stranger very much like me in another possible world) shows that the ‘two’ facts cannot be the same thing.
I don’t know
whether
Lewis addresses this sort of worry; I
don’t think he does in Plurality of
Worlds, at least. But there’s an obvious problem with the above
line of
reasoning: it commits the
Intensional Fallacy.
be identical to Clark
The Incredulous
Stare: There’s not much
to
be said
here, since it’s not really an argument. Nonetheless, the ‘argument’ of
the incredulous stare basically goes: “You believe in concrete possible
worlds that
are
spatio-temporally and causally isolated from us, and this
is what is supposed to ground modal facts? WTF?!?!” Followed
by an incredulous stare...
I suppose Lewis
can shrug his shoulders, scratch his head, or simply whistle dixie in
response.