First:
Some Key Terms Concepts.
Contingent:
Something is contingent if either (i) it does in fact exist but need
not have or (ii) it does not in fact exist, but it could have.
Most of the things in this world are contingent--rocks, trees,
computers, desks, you, me, etc.--because each one of these things does
in fact exist, but could easily have not existed (the computer you are
looking at might have not been made in the factory where it was in fact
made, your parents might not have met, and then there would be no you,
etc.). There are also, intuitively, a host of things that do not exist
but might have. Your parents might have had one more child than they
actually did, and so you could have had another sibling. This sibling
that does not exist but could have is also considered a contingent
thing.
Contingent things are often contrasted with
necessary things. Something is
necessary if it does in fact exist, and could not have failed to exist.
There aren't many things that people think that are necessary. Some
think that God is necessary--he does exist, and could not have failed
to exist. Other think that certain truths are necessary--e.g., 2 + 2 =
4 is in fact true, and it could not have failed to be true.
Possible
Worlds: In class, and on this handout
here, we discussed how
talk of what
could have been
and
had to have been and
could never be--i.e.,
possibility, necessity, and impossibility--is often discussed in terms
of possible worlds. If it's
possible that
p, then there is at least one
possible world where
p. If it
is
necessary that
p, then in all possible worlds,
p. If it is
impossible that
p, then in no possible world,
p.
So put in terms of possible world talk: A contingent being is a being
that exists in at least one possible world (which may not be the actual
world). A necessary being is one that exists in all possible worlds.
Gibbard symbolizes possibility by a diamond; necessity is symbolized
with a box. So, for example, this statement:
s
= c & [diamond] (s exists & c exists & ~ (s = c))
(Again, apologies for writing out the symbol "[diamond]"; I couldn't
get the symbols to post correctly.)
This statement means that a statue,
s,
and a piece of clay,
c, are
identical (e.g,
s =
c), but that it is also possible
that--i.e., there is a possible world where--
s exists and
c exists but
s and
c are
not identical. In other
words, Gibbard wants to endorse the claim that sometimes an object,
x, and an object,
y, are in fact identical (identical
in the actual world), but that they need not be (i.e.,
x and
y are not identical in some
possible world that is not the actual world).
Rea's
Assumptions vs. Our Commonsense Truisms
In the introduction, Rea posited what he called The Necessity
Assumption:
The
Necessity Assumption: For any objects x and y, if x is identical
with y, then it is necessary that x is identical with y. (p. xxiii MC)
This is the assumption that Gibbard is dropping in his "Contingent
Identity."
However, given how we formulated the material constitution puzzles by
our
7 commonsense truisms, we
don't have a Necessity Assumption. But we do have (7), Leibniz's Law.
We have seen that Leibniz's Law can apply to spatial properties,
temporal properties, and persistence conditions. It can also apply to
modal properties--i.e., what is and is not possible or necessary for an
object. In this way, we can subsume Rea's Necessity Assumption under
our principle (7), Leibniz's Law.
Goliath
and Lumpl
Gibbard makes heavy use of the Goliath and Lumpl puzzle, which was
discussed on this handout
here.
A
Posteriori Necessity
Consider some
a posteriori
identity claim such as Hesperus =
Phosphorus. It used to be, long ago, that people thought that Hesperus
and Phosphorus were different stars: they thought that Hesperus was a
star that rose in the evening, while Phosphorus was a different star
that rose in the morning. In fact, Hesperus and Phosphorus were the
same star, Venus. So we
discovered that
Hesperus = Phosphorus; it was an
a
posteriori identity claim.
Now, prior to Saul Kripke (1971, 1972), many thought that
a posteriori
identity claims were contingent. After all, it
seems true that it could have been
that Hesperus was not identical to Phosphorus; it
seems true that 'they' could have
been two distinct stars. And if so, then it is
contingent that Hesperus is
identical to Phosphorus. However, what Kripke pointed out was
that there is a difference between epistemic and metaphysical
possibility, and that
a posteriori
identities are metaphysically
necessary.
For consider: it could be that the astronomers were wrong and that
Hesperus is indeed distinct from Phosphorus. If so, then it seems that
it is possible that Hesperus (H) is not identical to Phosphorus (P).
And in this way,
for all we know,
it is possible that H is distinct from P. Yet notice that this can only
happen if we consider a situation where the actual world is one in
which--unbeknownst to the astronomers--H is in fact distinct from P.
But given that in the actual world, H = P, then it must be that
necessarily H = P. Kripke further showed that "[w]hether
something is a necessary truth...is not a matter of how we can know it,
but whether it might have been false if the world had been
different..." (p. 93-4 MC)
(We will discuss this in more detail in class.)
Kripke's
Theory of Proper Names and Rigid Designators
Kripke claims that when we use proper names such as "Goliath" and
"Lumpl" that these names are
rigid
designators--they rigidly pick out certain individuals in every
possible world (in which that individual exists). And we can then track
these individuals across possible worlds when we are considering the
particular individuals modal properties. So, for example, when I say
"George W. Bush could have been a circus clown" I mean to say of the
individual, picked out by the name "George W. Bush", that
he could have
been a circus clown. In terms of possible worlds, this means that there
is a possible world with George W. Bush being a circus clown.
For more information than you want to know about Kripke, go
here.
Second: Gibbard's Thesis
Gibbard does not want to dispute Kripke, but he does want to maintain
that sometimes--e.g., in puzzles cases such as Goliath and Lumpl--there
are indeed cases of
contingent
identity.
Gibbard argues for the identity of Goliath and Lumpl by appealing to
three reasons:
(i) first, "they" share all of the
"obvious" properties: i.e., shape, color, weight, location, etc.
(ii) it fits a "systematic account of statues and lumps of clay."
(iii) statues and lumps of clay are "part of the physical world, and we
ought...to have a systematic account of them."
His then turns to a theory of proper names (an alternative to Kripke's
theory) to account for the contingency of an identity statement such as
Goliath = Lumpl. Gibbard admits that if Kripke's theory of proper names
is correct, then Gibbard could not maintain his view about contingent
identity. However, Gibbard proposes a different view, insisting that it
(a) is a more plausible theory of proper names and (b) that it helps us
to solve material constitution puzzles such as Goliath and Lumpl.
One of the key moves here is to concentrate on just what is going on
when we say that some thing in one possible world is "the same thing
as" some thing in the actual world. On p. 99 Gibbard says:
"What, though, would constitute "that
same thing" is the statue and the piece of clay were different? Take
the situation in W' [where Goliath is not identical to Lumpl]: suppose
instead of breaking the statue, as I actually did, I had squeezed the
clay into a ball. Would that single thing which in fact I made and then
broke--which in fact was both a piece of clay and a statue--then be the
statue Goliath which I squeezed out of existence, or the piece of clay
Lumpl which went on existing after I squeezed it?...I can find no sense
in the question." (99 MC)
Moreover, he thinks that such a question only makes sense when we
consider what something is
designated
in a certain way. He claims:
"Proper names like "Goliath" or "Lumpl"
refer to a thing as
a thing of a certain kind: 'Goliath' refers to something as a statue;
'Lumpl', as a lump.For each such kind of thing, there is a set of
persistence criteria..." (100)
So
sortals, for Gibbard, are
important because they take a name like "Goliath" and make the name
rigid. Once we know what kind of thing something is, then, and only
then, can we track it across possible worlds and figure out its
persistence conditions.
As we will see in class, David Lewis will elaborate on this Contingent
Identity view, although with a slightly different (and radical)
view of possible worlds.
Page Last Updated: Feb.
12, 2008